Pain in Fish : a review of the evidence
Fisherman James D. Rose claims
that fish can't feel pain. He has published a paper stating that the
neocortex, the outer folded layer of the brain that is so highly
developed in humans, is the seat of all higher mental functions,
including consciousness of pain. Therefore, the neurological
machinery required to feel pain is missing in a fish, and indeed, is
present only in humans and apes. But, in focusing on a comparison of
the human brain with the fish brain alone, Rose's article seems
biased and anthropocentric.
Rose did not give a reason for his
assertion that consciousness depends, alone, on the neocortex. Nor
did his argument take into account the straightforward evolution of
the vertebrate brain. From fish to man, the brain has the same
structures, arranged in the same way, with the exception only of the
neocortex, which developed in mammals. Neurological studies have
shown that the newly evolved neocortex of mammals took over certain
higher functions, which were already present in fish, amphibians,
reptiles, and birds. (I. Glynn 1999)
The expansion of the forebrain has
occurred many times in different species, including in some fish,
whose brain structures would fall into Rose's category. All teleost
fishes (bony fishes) have elaborate forebrains (Butler and Hodos
1996) and the degree of forebrain development has been correlated
with social behaviour, and communication abilities, which are
considered to be integrated with cognition. (Kotrschal et al 1998).
Fish continue to develop neurons
throughout their lives, and do so at a faster rate when confronted
with a stimulating environment, indicating a link between experience
and neural development. For example, the triggerfish, (Balistidae),
which have advanced foraging techniques, have a relatively larger
telencephalon—the front part of the forebrain—than most other
families of fish investigated (Geiger 1956).
It is well established, for
example, that birds feel pain, and have advanced cognitive abilities.
Some species have better long term memories than humans, and others
far exceed us in visual recognition. Yet their little pea-brains lack
a neocortex. The miniaturization of the animal did not affect mental
capability (Barber 1993). Tests with birds
showed that higher mental capabilities could be found in a brain that
is wired differently than ours. Dolphins, too, show high cognitive
capabilities, but their brains have a different form than primate
brains, though both are mammals (Marino 2002). There are people in
which the expanded neo-cortex failed to develop, but who have normal
psychology and IQ's. (Edelman and Tononi 2000). So even in humans, it
seems that the neocortex is not necessary for consciousness.
Other researchers have concluded
that the neocortex was not central to consciousness. Donald R.
Griffin, (1998) theorized that the expanded human brain had allowed
the appearance of a complex subconscious mind. Since consciousness
was more likely to have been favoured by evolution due to its value
for survival, he considered it more probable that the centralization
of the nervous system had resulted in consciousness. No brain is
simple, as anyone who has observed the activities of a spider will
appreciate.
Laureys et al (2000), and other
researchers, found evidence that the thalamocortical system was the
essential neurological basis of conscious awareness, and Chapman and
Nakamura (1999) concluded that the neural systems involved in the
detection of tissue damage, (nociception) and the awareness of the
pain, likely evolved as an “interactive dynamic system” with the
cognitive processes, in the evolving central nervous system. These
findings and others suggested that it is the way the various regions
of the brain are integrated, that generates consciousness.
All of this easily available
evidence that contradicted Rose's conclusions, was omitted in his
article. He seemed to rely on the beliefs of fishermen, that the fish
brain was so simple that it was well understood, and that it could
not support consciousness. Unfortunately, fishermen had given it so
much publicity that people remembered only that science had proven
that fish don't feel pain. Some people started claiming that fish
were missing part of their brains!
Rose ascribed Pavlovian learning,
only, to fish, denying any possibility that consciousness could be
involved. Other researchers found evidence that showed otherwise, and
denied that learning in fish takes place in the total absence of
cognition and consciousness. (Maren 2001, Lovibond and Shanks 2002;
Overmier and Hollis, 1990). Chandroo et al (2004), acknowledged that
learning processes seen in fish, “may require the formation of
declarative memories.” (Declarative memories are memories of facts,
which we can call on to use, consciously, at any time). In reviewing
the relationship between learning in fish, memories, and conscious
cognition, Chandroo et al found that some fish behaviour is better
explained within a theoretical framework that includes primary
consciousness.
Fishermen will claim that fish
don't feel pain, because they have seen sharks continuing to function
in spite of terrible wounds. However, this is a common behaviour even
in humans. Fear is generated from deep in the brain and will
over-ride pain. The effect has an obvious benefit for survival.
Another argument declare that fish
cannot feel pain because sometimes a fish will bite a baited hook a
second time, after being unhooked and thrown back into the sea. But,
while it may be obvious to the fisherman what he is doing, how could
it be obvious to the fish? These men assumed that the fish understood
much more than it possibly could about its situation. It could have
no basis, among its experiences in life, for understanding the
fisherman's practice of deception—the possibility of a hook hidden
in the bit of food it had found.
It can see no dangerous predator
underwater, so how could it imagine that above the surface a man is
waiting, hoping to trick and kill it? Even a human walking by the sea
pursuing his own affairs, would never suspect that there was a
creature waiting for him beneath the surface with a plan to trap and
kill him. A fish that had already bitten a bit of food with a hook in
it, has no reason to assume that the next piece of food it finds will
also hide a hook.
But why ask those whose only
interest in fish is to kill them? There are people who have good will
towards fish : veterinarians. A bird specialist in Australia, Dr. Pat
Macwhirter, wrote to me that she had assisted in surgery on a fish
when a fish vet had come to work at her animal hospital. She
described the fish being more sensitive than birds to
electro-surgery, and said that the anaesthesia had to be deepened.
There was no doubt, she told me, that the fish had felt pain.
With their training in healing,
and experience with distressed animals, it seems to me that
veterinarians are in a much better position than fishermen to judge
whether or not an animal is in pain. I too had noted that the sharks
who had escaped being landed for finning, as well as female sharks
with extensive mating wounds, showed similar signs of pain as other
classes of animals. They were less alert, less reactive, and slower
moving.
Temple Grandin and Mark Deesing at
the American Board of Veterinary Practitioners Symposium of 2002
declared that “the ability of an animal to suffer from pain may be
related to the amount of associative neural circuitry linking
sub-cortical structures to higher levels of the nervous system.”
They considered that one could assume that an animal was in pain if
it actively sought pain relief, protected injured parts, became less
active when sick or injured, or self administered pain killing drugs,
all of which are seen in fish, whose bodies release strong
analgesics, which relieve pain.
The work of Dr. Lynne Sneddon, at
the University of Edinburgh revealed 58 receptors located on the
faces and heads of trout, that responded to harmful stimuli. They
resembled those in higher animals, including humans. A detailed map
was created of pain receptors in fish's mouths and all over their
bodies.
Dr. Sneddon injected the lips of
trout with acetic acid, bee venom, or saline solution as a control,
and found that those injected with the noxious substances showed
symptoms of pain, including an accelerated respiratory rate, rocking
back and forth on their pectoral fins, rubbing the affected areas on
the substrate, and taking longer to resume feeding than the control
group, whose behaviour remained normal. A morphine injection
significantly reduced these symptoms. (Sneddon, 2003)
The relief of the fishes’
symptoms by the pain reliever shows the interconnection between the
nociceptors, which sense the tissue damage, and the central nervous
system. Here was proof that fish are aware of tissue damage as pain.
Other researchers published papers
showing that fish vocalize when they feel threatened. I too, have
found that when I stroke triggerfish hiding in a cavity in the coral,
it squeaks at precisely at the moment of each caress.
Rebecca Dunlop of the Queens
University of Belfast, found that fish learn to avoid pain. She said:
“Pain avoidance in fish
doesn't seem to be a reflex response, rather one that is learned,
remembered and is changed according to different circumstances.
Therefore, if fish can perceive pain, then angling cannot continue to
be considered a non-cruel sport.”
When told of these findings, James
Rose replied: “One consequence, at least where I live, is that all
the revenues that support research on the habitat of fishes, that
monitor the health of the fish populations here—all the biologists
who do this work are funded by (fishing) licence revenues. If there
was no fishing there would be no one to do their job. That would be a
catastrophe. That would be a colossal loss, and believe me, there
would be no other funds from other sources to do the same job.”
(James D. Rose speaking to science reporter Abbie Thomas, the
producer of “All in the Mind,” at ABC)
This seemed a further indication
that his paper allegedly proving that fish don't feel pain was
politically motivated rather than an honest desire to find out the
truth. Note that he had done no study, as Dr. Lynne Sneddon did, to
determine whether fish feel pain or not. He had simply declared that
a difference between the human brain and the fish brain proved that
fish can't feel pain, while ignoring other relevant evidence.
And it can be argued that research
by and for sport fishermen is of questionable ultimate value since it
focuses only on the target species, to the neglect of the others in
the aquatic community, and is conducted in hope of favourable results for a political cause.
Sneddon's results have been found
since by other researchers who have further investigated the best way
to relieve pain in fish during surgery. (Harms et al. 2005) Pain
relief is now systematically used by veterinarians who perform
surgery on fish, in the full belief that they feel pain. It is now
believed that the pain system in fish is virtually the same as in
mammals.
It is daunting, how many people
remain proud of their efforts to outwit fish. They don't see the
irony in claiming that fish are too simple to feel pain, while being
proud of their ability to outwit them. This appears to be the
mindless acceptance of a tradition, resulting from a discovery in the
stone age, and, incredibly, still bragged about in the computer age.
References
Alexander RD
(1987) The biology of moral systems. Aldine de Gruiter, New YorkAronson LR (1951) Orientation and jumping behavior in the goby fish Bathygobius soporator. Am Mus Novitates 1486
Aronson LR (1956) Further studies on orientation and jumping behaviour in the goby fish Bathygobius soporator. Anat Rec 125:606
Bshary
R, Wickler W, Fricke H (2002) Fish cognition: a primate's eye view.
Animal Cognition (2002) 5 : 1-13
Colin PL (1972)
Daily activity patterns and effects of environmental conditions on
the behaviour of the yellowhead jawfish Opistognathus aurifrons,
with notes on its ecology. Zoologica 57:137-169Colin PL (1973) Burrowing behaviour of the yellowhead jawfish, Opistognathus aurifrons. Copeia 1973:84-90
Barber TX (1993) The Human Nature of Birds. Bookman Press, Melbourne
Clutten-Brock
TH, Parker GA (1995) Punishment in animal societies. Nature
373:209-215
Chandroo
KP, Yue S, and Mocci RD (2004) An evaluation of current perspectives
on consciousness and pain in fishes. Fish and Fisheries 5. 281-295
Chapman,
CR and Nakamura Y (1999) A passion of the soul: an introduction to
pain for consciousness researchers. Consciousness and Cognition 8.
391-422
Dugatkin
LA, Wilson DS (1993) Fish behaviour, partner choice, and cognitive
ethology. Rev Fish Biol Fish 3:368-372
Duzer
EM van (1939) Observations on the breeding habits of the cut-lip
minnow, Exoglossum maxillingua. Copeia 1939:65-75
Fricke
H (1971) Fische als Feinde tropischer Seeigel. Mar Biol 9:328-338
Edelman
GM and Tononi G (2000)A Universe of Consciousness. Basic Books, New
York, NY
Glynn
I. (1999) An Anatomy of Thought: The Origin and Machinery of the
Mind. Wiedenfield and Nicholson
Geiger
W (1956) Quantitative Untersuchungen über das Gehirn der
Knochenfische, mit besonderer Berücksichtigung seines relativen
Wachstums, I Acta Anat 26: 121-163
Grandin
T. and Deesing M. American Board of Veterinary Practitioners -
Symposium 2002 May 17, 2002, Special Session Pain, Stress, Distress
and Fear. Emerging Concepts and Strategies in Veterinary Medicine
Griffin
DR (1998) Animal Minds. The University of Chicago Press.
Grutter
AS 1995 Relationships between cleaning rates and ectoparasite loads
in coral reef fishes. Mar Ecol Prog Ser 118:51-58
Harmes
CA, Lewbart GA, Swanson CR, Kishimori JM, Boylan SM (2005)
Behavioural and Clinical Pathology Changes in Koi Carp (Cyprinus
carpio) Subjected to Anaesthesia
and Surgery with and without Intra-Operative Analgesics. Comparative
Medicine Vol. 55 No. 3 221-226
Kacher
H (1963) Opithognathus aurifrons (Opisthognathidae) Graben
einer Wohnhöhle, Wallbau Film E514, Encyclopaedia Cinematographica.
Institut für den wissenschaftlichen Film, Göttingen
Lachner
A (1952) Studies of the biology of the cyprinid fish of the chub
genus Nocomis of northeastern United States. Am Midl Nat 48:433-466
Laureys
S., Faymonville ME, Luxon A, Lamy M, Franck G, and Maquet P (2000)
Restoration of thalamocortical connectivity after recovery from
persistent
Lovibond
PF , Shanks DR (2002) The role of awareness in Pavlovian
conditioning: empirical evidence and theoretical implication.
Journal of Experimental Psychology 28 3-26
Maren
S (2001) Neurobiology of Pavlovian fear conditioning. Annual Review
of Neuroscience 24. 897-931
Marino
L (2002) Convergence of complex cognitive abilities in cetaceans and
primates. Brain, Behaviour and Evolution 59. 21-32
Milinski
M, Pfluger D, Külling D, Kettler R (1990b) Do sticklebacks
cooperate repeatedly in reciprocal pairs? Behav Ecol Sociobiol
27:17-21
Morris
D (1958) The reproductive behaviour of the ten-spined stickleback
(Pygosteus pungitius L.). Behaviour [Suppl] 6:1-154
Myrberg
AA, Riggio RJ (1985) Acoustically mediated individual recognition by
a coral reef fish (Pomacentrus portitus)
Myrberg
AA, Montgomery WL, Fishelson L (1988) The reproductive behaviour of
Acanthurus nigrofuscus (Forskal) and other surgeon fishes
(Fam. Acanthuridae) of Eilat, Israel (Gulf of Aqaba, Red Sea).
Ethology 79:31-61
Nowak
MA, Sigmund K (1998) Evolution of indirect reciprocity by image
scoring. Nature 393:573-577
Overmier
JB, Hollis KL (1990) Fish in the think tank: learning, memory, and
integrated behaviour. Neurobiology of Comparative Cognition (eds
Kesner RP, Olson DS), Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsday, NJ. pp. 205-236
Roberts
G (1998) Competitive altruism: from reciprocity to the handicap
principle. Proc R Soc Lond B 265:427-431
Rose,
JD 2002 The neurobehavioural nature of fishes, and the question of
awareness and pain. Rev. Fish. Sci. 10:1-38
Sneddon,
LU 2003. The evidence for pain in fish: The use of morphine as an
analgesic. Applied Animal Behavior Science. 83:153-162.
Zahavi
A (1995) Altruism as a handicap—the limitations of kin selection
and reciprocity. J Avian Biol 26:1-3
Comments